Friday, May 1, 2015

Final Blog Post - Institutional Loyalty



Institutional Loyalty

In 2011 Aaron Swartz, was arrested for downloading nearly five million files from JSTOR, a digital library of mass academic journals, by infiltrating a network on the Massachusetts Institute of Technology campus. Swartz was caught on camera by MIT when he was re-entering the network closet to replace the storage devices he was using at the time to hold the downloaded information. Swartz believed that information should not be wholesaled, especially when the research for the journals were funded by tax dollars. He believed that the information should have been open source, and available to anyone interested, for free. Swartz only downloaded these journals and did not release them, however, MIT filed charges. Due to the lack of institutional loyalty, MIT concluded that this downloading was theft before any other possibility. The prosecutors on this case pushed for the firmest penalties, and MIT stood silently by and watched. These criminal charges led to Swartz taking his own life in 2013.

The heart of this institutional disloyalty comes from MIT’s contradictory tradition of encouraging its colleagues to follow their curiosity wherever it may lead them, even if that’s somewhere they are not authorized. MIT’s main lobby doors are always unlocked, and the computer networks are set up for easy guest access. The concept of sharing information, the same one that Swartz stood for, was born in MIT’s computer labs in the 1950’s and 60’s. Due to this many say that MIT has Swartz’s blood on its hands. MIT could have asked for the charges to be dropped just like JSTOR did. Instead, the university chose to remain neutral, and in doing so contradicted its adopted culture that encourages openness.

How could a university that boasts about its community of hackers and hackers abilities turn around and let a member of that community be prosecuted? Every year MIT holds a self-declared hackathon where students are asked to show off their hacker abilities, the results are then posted on MIT’s site and can be read here. This begs the question of where MIT’s obligation and/or loyalty reside. Is it with their self-produced hacker community, or with obsolete and unjust laws? I believe MIT should not contradictorily prosecute hackers for their success and abilities. Philosopher Josiah Royce argued that as a member of a group, “We share the standards of that group”. With this in mind, MIT is the leader of a group, and should set equal standards for all while reaming loyal to that culture. Royce also argued that loyalty gives security, and offers ready-made standards. This holds very true to this case. MIT should have remained loyal to Swartz and his quest to share information paid for by the public, to the public. Another philosopher, W.E.B. DuBois also argued that values are bound up with social group identity. DuBois stated, “We are members of a nation first, then of a culture, and then a subculture, and we may adopt values consistent with loyalty to those groups”. The group in question here is the hacker community. With being a “hacker” there is a hacker ethic or philosophy that is adopted. The vital topics within these ethics are access to information, freedom of information, and improvement to quality of life via information. This is what Swartz was striving for, and MIT put a stop to. 


I agree with philosopher John Riser and his stance on obligation to society and loyalty to community. He argued that obligations are displayed toward rules or requirements of formalized roles stemming from a membership in society. I believe that MIT should have been obligated to take a stance in the Swartz case to protect the community that it cultivates. Instead they remained silent and in the process of doing so, the community tragically lost a valuable member.





Sources:

No comments:

Post a Comment